The path difference between two waves reaching a point on the screen from the two slits determines whether they interfere constructively or destructively.
It is given by:
Δx = d sin(θ)
where d is the distance between the slits and θ is the angle between the line joining the point on the screen and the central axis.
For constructive interference to occur, the path difference Δx must be an integer multiple of the wavelength of the light (λ).
Mathematically, this condition can be expressed as:
Δx = mλ
where m is an integer (0, 1, 2, ...).
For destructive interference to occur, the path difference Δx must be an odd multiple of half the wavelength of the light (λ/2).
Mathematically, this condition can be expressed as:
Δx = (2m + 1)λ/2
where m is an integer (0, 1, 2, ...).
The intensity \( I \) of light at a point on the screen can be expressed as:
\( I = I_0 \cos^2(\phi) \)
Where:
The intensity of light at each point depends on the interference pattern, with bright fringes corresponding to constructive interference and dark fringes corresponding to destructive interference.
The phase difference \( \phi \) can be related to the path difference \( \Delta x \) using the wave number \( k \) (related to the wavelength \( \lambda \)):
\( \phi = \frac{2\pi}{\lambda} \Delta x \)
So, the intensity at a point on the screen depends on the path difference \( \Delta x \), which in turn depends on the distance from the slits and the angle at which the light reaches that point.
The brightness of the light at different points on the screen in the double-slit experiment is determined by the interference pattern, with bright fringes corresponding to constructive interference and dark fringes corresponding to destructive interference.
In a double-slit experiment, a particle (such as a photon) emitted from a source S can reach a detector D by taking two different paths, e.g., through an upper or a lower slit in a barrier between the source and the detector. After sufficiently many repetitions of this experiment, we can evaluate the frequency of clicks in the detector D and show that it is inconsistent with the predictions based on probability theory. Let us use the quantum approach to show how the discrepancy arises.
The particle emitted from S can reach detector D by taking two different paths, which are assigned probability amplitudes z1 and z2, respectively. We may then say that the upper slit is taken with probability p1 = |z1|² and the lower slit with probability p2 = |z2|². These are two mutually exclusive events. With the two slits open, allowing the particle to take either path, probability theory declares (by the Kolmogorov additivity axiom) that the particle should reach the detector with probability p1 + p2 = |z1|² + |z2|². But this is not what happens experimentally!
That is, if one happens then the other one cannot. For example, "heads" and "tails" are mutually exclusive outcomes of flipping a coin, but "heads" and "6" are not mutually exclusive outcomes of simultaneously flipping a coin and rolling a dice.
Let us see what happens if we instead follow the two "quantum rules": first, we add the amplitudes, then we square the absolute value of the sum to get the probability. Thus, the particle will reach the detector with probability
\( p = |z|^2 \)
\( = |z_1 + z_2|^2 \)
\( = |z_1|^2 + |z_2|^2 + z_1^* z_2 + z_1 z_2^* \)
\( = p_1 + p_2 + |z_1| \cdot |z_2| (e^{i(\phi_2 - \phi_1)} + e^{-i(\phi_2 - \phi_1)}) \)
\( = p_1 + p_2 + 2p_1 p_2 \cos(\phi_2 - \phi_1) \)
The appearance of the interference terms marks the departure from the classical theory of probability. The probability of any two seemingly mutually exclusive events is the sum of the probabilities of the individual events modified by the interference term. Depending on the relative phase φ2 - φ1, the interference term can be either negative (destructive interference) or positive (constructive interference), leading to either suppression or enhancement, respectively, of the total probability p.
The algebra is simple; our focus is on the physical interpretation. Firstly, note that the important quantity here is the relative phase φ2 - φ1 rather than the individual phases φ1 and φ2. This observation implies that the particle reacts only to the difference of the two phases, each pertaining to a separate path. Secondly, what has happened to the additivity axiom in probability theory? What was wrong with it? One problem is the assumption that the processes of taking the upper or the lower slit are mutually exclusive; in reality, as we have just mentioned, the two transitions both occur simultaneously.
According to the philosopher Karl Popper (1902–1994), a theory is genuinely scientific only if it is possible, in principle, to establish that it is false. Genuinely scientific theories are never finally confirmed because, no matter how many confirming observations have been made, observations that are inconsistent with the empirical predictions of the theory are always possible. There is no fundamental reason why Nature should conform to the additivity axiom.
We find out how nature works by making "intelligent" guesses, running experiments, checking what happens, and formulating physical theories. If our guess disagrees with experiments, then it is wrong, so we try another intelligent guess, and another, etc. Right now, quantum theory is the best guess we have: it offers good explanations and predictions that have not been falsified by any of the existing experiments. This said, rest assured that one day quantum theory will be falsified, and then we will have to start guessing all over again.